You can edit almost every page by Creating an account. Otherwise, see the FAQ.

Richard Maxwell Gaskin

From EverybodyWiki Bios & Wiki






Richard Maxwell Gaskin
Born (1960-05-08) 8 May 1960 (age 64)
Glasgow, United Kingdom
🏫 EducationUniversity College Oxford
💼 Occupation

Search Richard Gaskin on Amazon.

Richard Maxwell Gaskin (born 1960) is a British philosopher and Professor at the University of Liverpool. He has published on Metaphysics, Philosophy of Language and Logic, and History of Philosophy, as well as on Philosophy of Literature, Literary theory, and the European literary tradition. Gaskin received his BA, BPhil, and DPhil in Classics and Philosophy at University College, Oxford, and has held academic posts at St. Edmund Hall, Oxford, as well as at the University of Sussex.[1]

Gaskin is the author of many published articles and nine books, including: Language and World: A Defence of Linguistic Idealism (2020), Tragedy and Redress in Western Literature: a Philosophical Perspective (2018), Language, Truth, and Literature: a Defence of Literary Humanism (2013), The Unity of the Proposition (2008), Experience and the World's Own Language: a Critique of John McDowell's Empiricism (2006), and The Sea Battle and the Master Argument: Aristotle and Diodorus Cronus on the metaphysics of the future (1995).[2]

Early life, education, and career[edit]

Gaskin was born in 1960 in Milngavie, Glasgow, and attended Robert Gordon's College, Aberdeen, where his father, Professor Maxwell Gaskin DFC, held the Jaffrey Chair of Political Economy.[3] He studied Literae Humaniores (Classics and Philosophy) at University College, Oxford, and obtained his BA (first class) in 1982. While an undergraduate at Oxford he was secretary of the Oxford University Dramatic Society from 1981 to 82, and directed a production of Marlowe’s Dr Faustus at the Oxford Playhouse in March 1981.[4] He took the BPhil exam in 1986, supervised by John McDowell. In 1987 he won the Gaisford Dissertation Prize in classical literature for his essay Tragedy and Subjectivity in Virgil’s 'Aeneid' .[5] He was awarded the DPhil in 1988 for a thesis supervised by Michael Dummett, David Wiggins, and Barry Stroud, entitled Experience, Agency, and the Self.[6] From 1988 to 1989 Gaskin spent a year as an Alexander von Humboldt visiting fellow at the University of Mainz, Germany, researching decision-making in classical literature under the Virgilian scholar Antonie Wlosok.[7] From 1991 to 2001, he was a Lecturer (from 1997 Reader) in Philosophy at the University of Sussex.[8] In 2001 he became Professor in the Department of Philosophy at the University of Liverpool.[9]

Philosophical work[edit]

A central part of Gaskin’s work focuses on the doctrine of linguistic idealism, the idea that the world is produced by, and depends on, language. Gaskin argues that the dependence of the world on language is a logical and constitutive one, rather than a temporal one: objects (such as tables and chairs) exist in virtue of, and are constituted as objects by, the existence of sentences about them; language 'makes the world', but not in the sense that there was a time at which it pre-existed the world. Although human language is a purely contingent product of evolution, there is a transcendental sense in which the existence of the world depends on the existence of language—more precisely, on the capacity of language to talk about the world. In Gaskin’s view the world is constitutively composed of propositions, which are referents of sentences; these propositions contain the ordinary objects of our discourse. In Language and World (2020), Gaskin develops the theory of linguistic idealism and defends it against several objections. He addresses the problem that some mathematical entities, in particular uncomputable sets of real numbers, cannot be distinguished by language; he does this by developing a ‘split-level' version of linguistic idealism. In his approach all the basic entities of the world can be named in language, and all further entities, even if they cannot be named, can be derived from these basic entities by describable constructive operations. In Tragedy and Redress in Western Literature: A Philosophical Perspective (2018), Gaskin argues that not even the tragic aspects of life (such as pain and suffering) are beyond language, an objection commonly raised against the idea that language is omnicompetent to talk about and describe reality.

In his writings on literature, Gaskin has defended a version of literary humanism, according to which works of imaginative literature have an objective meaning which is fixed at the time of their production and is the same for all readers.[10] In addition to his publications in philosophy of literature, he has written a study of the poets Horace and Housman[11], essays on Virgil (e.g. On being pessimistic about the end of the 'Aeneid'[12]), Homer (e.g. Do Homeric Heroes make real decisions?[13]), the classicist Richard Bentley,[14] and the essayist Charles Lamb.[15] Gaskin has translated selections from Apollonius of Rhodes's Greek poem Argonautica into English verse.[16] Gaskin has written on ancient and on medieval philosophy [17] [18], and on Wittgenstein.[19] He maintains a website on which he mounts recordings of English, German, and Latin poetry.[20]

Publications [2][21][edit]

Books[edit]

Language and world: a Defence of Linguistic Idealism (London/New York: Routledge, forthcoming 2020). ISBN 978-0-367-90258-2 Search this book on ..

Tragedy and Redress in Western Literature: a Philosophical Perspective (London/New York: Routledge, 2018). ISBN 978-1-138-49808-2 Search this book on ..

Horace and Housman (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2013). ISBN 978-1-137-36292-6 Search this book on ..

Language, Truth, and Literature: a Defence of Literary Humanism (Oxford: OUP, 2013). ISBN 978-0-198-77689-5 Search this book on ..

The Unity of the Proposition (Oxford: OUP, 2008). ISBN 978-0-199-23945-0 Search this book on ..

Experience and the World’s Own Language: a Critique of John McDowell’s Empiricism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2006). ISBN 978-0-199-28725-3 Search this book on ..

Grammar in Early Twentieth-Century Philosophy, edited collection with contributions from Stewart Candlish, Gary Ebbs, Richard Gaskin, James Levine, Richard Mendelsohn, Alex Oliver, Graham Priest, Ian Proops, Bede Rundle und Peter Simons (London: Routledge, 2001). ISBN 978-0-415-40845-5 Search this book on .

Simplicius on Aristotle Categories 9–15, an annotated translation of Simplicius’ commentary on Aristotle’s Categories, chs. 9–15 (London: Duckworth, 2000). ISBN 978-0-715-62900-0 Search this book on ..

The Sea Battle and the Master Argument: Aristotle and Diodorus Cronus on the Metaphysics of the Future (Berlin/ New York: Walter de Gruyter, 1995). ISBN 978-3-11-014430-7 Search this book on ..

Selected articles[edit]

On being pessimistic about the end of the Aeneid, forthcoming in Harvard Studies in Classical Philology [22].

A Defence of the Resemblance Meaning of “What it’s like”, Mind 128, 2019, 673–98. DOI 10.1093/mind/fzx023.

From the unity of the proposition to linguistic idealism, Synthese 196, 2019, 1325–42. DOI 10.1007/s11229-016-1081-5.

Identity and Reference in a Black Universe, in P. Stalmaszczyk ed., Philosophical and Linguistic Analyses of Reference (Frankfurt: Lang, 2016), 19–41. DOI 10.3726/978-3-653-05429-3.

The Identity Theory of Truth, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, published May 1, 2015.

Meaning, Normativity, and Naturalism, in B. Dainton and H. Robinson eds., The Bloomsbury Companion to Analytic Philosophy (London: Bloomsbury, 2013), 230–54. ISBN 978-1-474-23648-5 Search this book on ..

Reach’s Puzzle and Mention (co-authored with Daniel Hill), Dialectica 67, 2013, 201–22. DOI 10.1111/1746-8361.12021.

When Logical Atomism met the Theaetetus: Ryle on Naming and Saying, in M. Beaney ed., The Oxford Handbook of the History of Analytic Philosophy (Oxford: OUP, 2013), 851–69. DOI 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199238842.013.0037.

On Neutral Relations (co-authored with Daniel Hill), Dialectica 66, 2012, 167–86. DOI 10.1111/j.1746-8361.2012.01294.x.

Reference and the Permutation Argument, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 111, 2011, 295–309. DOI 10.1111/j.1467-9264.2011.00310.x.

The Unity of the Proposition: Reply to Denyer, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 88, 2011, 729–30. DOI 10.1080/00048402.2010.511649.

Bentley’s classicism, Paradise Lost, and the Schema Horatianum, International Journal of the Classical Tradition 17, 2010, 354–65. DOI 10.2307/40931338.

The Unity of the Proposition: Replies to Vallicella, Schnieder, and García-Carpintero, Dialectica 64, 2010, 259–64 and 303–11 (Book symposium on The Unity of the Proposition). DOI 10.1111/j.1746-8361.2009.01212.x

Realism and the Picture Theory of Meaning, Philosophical Topics 37, 2009, 49–62. DOI 10.5840/philtopics200937115.

Bradleys Regress und die Einheit der Proposition, Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 57, 2009, 575–82. DOI 10.1524/dzph.2009.57.4.575.

John Wyclif and the Theory of Complexly Signifiables, Vivarium 47, 2009, 74–96. DOI 10.1163/156853408X345927.

Complexe Significabilia and Aristotle’s Categories, in J. Biard und I. Rosier-Catach eds., La Tradition Médiévale des Catégories (Louvain: Peeters, 2003), 187–205. ISBN 90-429-1335-5 Search this book on ..

Proposition and World, Introduction to R. Gaskin ed., Grammar in Early Twentieth-Century Philosophy (London: Routledge, 2001), 1–27. ISBN 978-0-415-40845-5 Search this book on ..

Nonsense and Necessity in Wittgenstein’s Mature Philosophy, in R. Gaskin ed., Grammar in Early Twentieth-Century Philosophy (London: Routledge, 2001), 199–217. ISBN 978-0-415-40845-5 Search this book on ..

Ockham’s Mental Language, Connotation, and the Inherence Regress, in D. Perler ed., Ancient and Medieval Theories of Intentionality (Leiden: Brill, 2001), 227–63. ISBN 978-9-004-12295-6 Search this book on ..

Do Homeric Heroes make Real Decisions? (revised version of 1990 CQ paper), in D. Cairns ed., Oxford Readings on Homer’s Iliad (Oxford: Clarendon, 2001), 147–65. ISBN 978-0-198-72182-6 Search this book on ..

Die Einheit der Aussage, in U. Meixner ed., Metaphysik im postmetaphysischen Zeitalter/Metaphysics in the Post-Metaphysical Age (Vienna: öbv, 2001), 305–10. ISBN 978-3-209-03194-5 Search this book on ..

Tense Logic and the Master Argument, Philosophiegeschichte und logische Analyse 2, 1999, 202–24. DOI 10.30965/26664275-00201015.

Predication and Ontology: Reply to Denyer, Philosophy 73, 1998, 625–9. DOI 10.1017/S0031819198004082.

The Unity of the Declarative Sentence, Philosophy 73, 1998, 21–45. DOI 10.1017/S0031819197000065.

Fatalism, Bivalence, and the Past, Philosophical Quarterly 48, 1998, 83–8. DOI10.1111/1467-9213.00083.

Fatalism, Middle Knowledge, and Comparative Similarity of Worlds, Religious Studies 34, 1998, 189–203. DOI 10.1017/S0034412598004338.

Simplicius on the Meaning of Sentences: a Commentary on In Cat. 396,30–397,28, Phronesis 43, 1998, 42–62. DOI 10.1163/15685289860517793.

“Socrates is identical”: Wittgenstein and Categorical Nonsense, in P. Weingartner et al. eds., The Role of Pragmatics in Contemporary Philosophy: Papers of the 20th International Wittgenstein Symposium vol. 5 (Kirchberg, 1997), 273–8.

Peter Damian on Divine Power and the Contingency of the Past, British Journal of the History of Philosophy 5, 1997, 229–47. DOI 10.1080/09608789708570965.

Russell and Richard Brinkley on the Unity of the Proposition, History and Philosophy of Logic 18, 1997, 139–50. DOI 10.1080/01445349708837284.

Überlegungen zur Identitätstheorie der Prädikation, Wissenschaft und Weisheit 60, 1997, 87–103.

Peter of Ailly and other Fourteenth-Century Thinkers on Divine Power and the Necessity of the Past, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 79, 1997, 273–91. DOI 10.1515/agph.1997.79.3.273.

The Stoics on Cases, Predicates and the Unity of the Proposition, in Aristotle and After ed. R. Sorabji (London: Institute of Classical Studies, 1997), 91–108. DOI 10.1111/j.2041-5370.1997.tb02264.x.

Fregean Sense and Russellian Propositions, Philosophical Studies 86, 1997, 131–54. DOI 10.1023/A:1017929320501

Reconstructing the Master Argument of Diodorus Cronus: Response to Denyer, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 78, 1996, 181–91.

“Kein Etwas, aber auch nicht ein Nichts!”: kann die Grammatik tatsächlich täuschen?, Grazer Philosophische Studien 51, 1996, 85–104.

Sea Battles, Worn-out Cloaks, and Other Matters of Interpretation: Weidemann on Aristotle’s Peri Hermeneias, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 78, 1996, 48–60. DOI 10.1515/agph.1996.78.1.48.

Truth, Fiction, and Literature, British Journal of Aesthetics 35,1995, 395–401. DOI 10.1093/bjaesthetics/35.4.395.

Middle Knowledge: Reply to Rice, Philosophical Quarterly 45, 1995, 505–9. DOI 10.2307/2220315.

Experience and Criteria, Archiv für Begriffsgeschichte 38, 1995, 261–75. JSTOR EXPERIENCE AND CRITERIA.

Bradley's Regress, The Copula and the Unity of the Proposition, Philosophical Quarterly 45, 1995, 161–80. DOI 10.2307/2220413.

Aeneas Ultor and the Problem of Pietas, Eirene 30, 1994, 70–96.

Truth, Meaning, and Literature, British Journal of Aesthetics 34, 1994, 392–9. DOI 10.1093/bjaesthetics/34.4.382

Molina on Divine Foreknowledge and the Principle of Bivalence, Journal of the History of Philosophy 32, 1994, 27–47. DOI 10.1353/hph.1994.0081.

Fatalism, Foreknowledge, and the Reality of the Future, The Modern Schoolman 71, 1994, 83–113. DOI 10.5840/schoolman199471211.

The Truth in Fiction, British Journal of Aesthetics 33, 1993, 177–9. DOI 10.1093/bjaesthetics/33.2.177.

Conditionals of Freedom and Middle Knowledge Philosophical Quarterly 43, 1993, 412–30. (Winner of 1992 PQ essay competition.) DOI 10.2307/2219983. Reprinted with corrections in E. Dekker et al. eds., Middle Knowledge (Peter Lang, 2000), 137–56, ISBN 978-3-631-36288-4 Search this book on ..

Alexander’s Sea Battle: a discussion of Alexander of Aphrodisias De Fato 10, Phronesis 38, 1993, 75–94. DOI 10.1163/156852893321052460.

Turnus, Mezentius, and the Complexity of Virgil’s Aeneid, Latomus, Studies in Latin Literature and Roman History VI, 1992, 295–316, ISBN 978-2-870-31157-8 Search this book on ..

Do Homeric Heroes make Real Decisions?, Classical Quarterly 40, 1990, 1–15. DOI 10.1017/S0009838800026768.

Platonism and Forms of Life, Auslegung 16, 1989, 1–16. DOI 10.17161/AJP.1808.9311.

Can Aesthetic Value Be Explained?, British Journal of Aesthetics 29, 1989, 329–40. DOI 10.1093/bjaesthetics/29.4.329.

External links[edit]

Richard Gaskin at the University of Liverpool, Philosophy.

Richard Gaskin on Academia.edu

The Literary Voice

References[edit]

  1. The Sea Battle and the Master Argument: Aristotle and Diodorus Cronus on the Metaphysics of the Future (Berlin/ New York: Walter de Gruyter, 1995), page VII
  2. 2.0 2.1 "Richard Gaskin at Google Books".
  3. "Obituary of Professor Maxwell Gaskin". thetimes.co.uk.
  4. "Stage". warwick.ac.uk.
  5. "St Edmund Hall Magazine 1986-87".
  6. Gaskin, Richard M. (Richard Maxwell) (24 April 1988). Experience, agency and the self (Thesis). University of Oxford – via ora.ox.ac.uk.
  7. "Blurb to 'Do Homeric Heroes Make Real Decisions?'".
  8. Gaskin, Richard (18 April 2013). Blurb to Language, Truth, and Literature. ISBN 9780199657902. Search this book on
  9. "Richard Gaskin - University of Liverpool". www.liverpool.ac.uk.
  10. "Review of Gaskin's Language, Truth, and Literature".
  11. Horace and Housman (New York, 2013) – via www.academia.edu. Search this book on
  12. Gaskin, Richard. "On being pessimistic about the end of the Aeneid".
  13. Gaskin, Richard (1990). "Do Homeric Heroes make Real Decisions?". The Classical Quarterly. 40 (1): 1–15. doi:10.1017/S0009838800026768 – via www.academia.edu.
  14. Gaskin, Richard. "Bentley's classicism, Paradise Lost, and the Schema Horatianum" – via www.academia.edu.
  15. Gaskin, Richard. "Lamb and Horace". Charles Lamb Bulletin – via www.academia.edu.
  16. Apollonius of Rhodes: the voyage of Argo : passages from the first three books translated into English verse, with a brief linking narrative. Leerie Books. 3 May 1995. OCLC 35137372. Search this book on
  17. Gaskin, Richard (2009). "John Wyclif and the Theory of Complexly Signifiables". Vivarium. 47 (1): 74–96. doi:10.1163/156853408X345927 – via www.academia.edu.
  18. The Sea Battle and the Master Argument: Aristotle and Diodorus Cronus on the Metaphysics of the Future (De Gruyter 1995) – via www.academia.edu. Search this book on
  19. Gaskin, Richard. "Nonsense and necessity in Wittgenstein's mature philosophy" – via www.academia.edu.
  20. "The Literary Voice".
  21. "Richard Gaskin - University of Liverpool". www.liverpool.ac.uk.
  22. Gaskin, Richard. "On being pessimistic about the end of the Aeneid (Final version)" – via www.academia.edu.

Removed references to Gaskin's CV, so that the facts are now established by neutral, external sources.[edit]


This article "Richard Gaskin" is from Wikipedia. The list of its authors can be seen in its historical and/or the page Edithistory:Richard Gaskin. Articles copied from Draft Namespace on Wikipedia could be seen on the Draft Namespace of Wikipedia and not main one.

Page kept on Wikipedia This page exists already on Wikipedia.